Chapter 2 Topics in drug therapy
Practical prescribing
The case histories are all real. The data given in the text and figures come from a study commissioned by the General Medical Council.1
Prescribing
Getting it right
Good prescribing starts with taking a good history:
• Does your patient have other medical conditions – some may be worsened by treatment you would normally give for their presenting complaint.
• What drugs is your patient taking now? What are they for? Are they all still needed? Could they be causing the symptoms or signs that have brought the patient to you? Could they interact with whatever you might think of prescribing?
• What drugs has your patient taken in the past? Why were they stopped? Did they cause side-effects?
• Is the patient allergic to any drugs?
• Are they taking any non-prescription (over-the-counter) drugs? If so, could they interact with whatever you might prescribe (for example, St John’s wort is an enzyme-inducer)?
• Making a diagnosis – or at least having a range of possibilities. Know what it is you are wishing to achieve and the evidence for the likely efficacy of the drug treatment you wish to give.
• Knowing your patient’s kidney and liver function – most drugs are eliminated by these organs; and some drugs can damage them.
• Getting the dose right. For many drugs you will not know the dose, so do not pretend you do. Never, ever guess. Never be afraid to ask. Never be too busy to look up a dose – better to check now than make a trip to the Coroner’s Court later.
• Explaining to your patient why you think this treatment will work, the likelihood of it working, the more common side-effects and what your plans are if it does not work.
• Being alert to the development of adverse drug reactions. If a patient develops new symptoms after starting a drug, it is probably the drug. If the adverse effect is in a fairly new drug – or is not already well known – you should report the event to the national body responsible for monitoring and recording adverse drug reactions.
• Being very clear about what it is you are prescribing.
• If using a hand-written prescription, write clearly.
• If working in a different hospital, remember that the prescription chart may not be the same as where you have just been.
• If using electronic prescribing, beware drop-down menus and drugs with similar looking names, e.g. carbimazole and carbamazepine.
Examples of when things went wrong
Forgetting that a newly prescribed drug can interact with long-term drug treatment
A 64-year-old man had been taking warfarin for many years. He developed a chest infection and an out of hours doctor prescribed amoxicillin. Later that week he was admitted with a large, painful right knee haemarthrosis and an INR > 10 (see p. 489). New drugs may interact with those the patient has been taking for a long time!
Why do mistakes happen?
There are also factors specific to the medical environment, including:
• Not familiar with the drug chart (usually on moving to a new hospital).
• Unfamiliar patient – and not taking the time to become familiar with the full medical and drug history.
• Arithmetical errors in calculating dose.
• Omitting drugs for a newly admitted patient because of inadequate information.
When lack of knowledge does play a part, it is often the flawed application of knowledge in that particular patient – i.e. the right drug for the presenting condition, but the wrong drug for that patient because of coexisting medical or drug factors.
The General Medical Council expects that, by the time they graduate, medical students will be able to:2
• Prescribe drugs safely, effectively and economically.
• Establish an accurate drug history, covering both prescribed and other medication.
• Plan appropriate drug therapy for common indications, including pain and distress.
• Provide a safe and legal prescription.
• Calculate appropriate drug doses and record the outcome accurately.
• Provide patients with appropriate information about their medicines.
• Access reliable information about medicines.
• Detect and report adverse drug reactions.
• Demonstrate awareness that many patients use complementary and alternative therapies, and awareness of the existence and range of these therapies, why patients use them, and how this might affect other types of treatment that patients are receiving.
The therapeutic situation
Some background
Remarkably, this system persisted among ‘learned and rational’ (i.e. university-trained) physicians until it was challenged in the 17th century. Thomas Sydenham3 (1624–1689) showed that during epidemics, many people could suffer the same disease, and different epidemics had distinct characteristics. Later, Giovanni Morgagni (1682–1771), by correlating clinical and autopsy findings, demonstrated that diseases related to particular organs. Now the study of disease, rather than the patient, became the centre of attention. Yet it was only in the 19th century that medicine developed as a science, when the microscope revealed the cell as the basic construction unit of the body and specific entities of pathology became recognisable, most notably in the case of infection with microorganisms (‘germ theory’).
Throw out opium …; throw out a few specifics …; throw out wine, which is a food, and the vapours which produce the miracle of anaesthesia, and I firmly believe that if the whole materia medica, as now used, could be sunk to the bottom of the sea, it would be all the better for mankind, – and all the worse for the fishes…4
Treating patients with drugs
A book can provide knowledge and contribute to the formation of judgement, but it can do little to impart skill and wisdom, which are the products of example of teachers and colleagues, of experience and of innate and acquired capacities. But: ‘It is evident that patients are not treated in a vacuum and that they respond to a variety of subtle forces around them in addition to the specific therapeutic agent.’5
When a patient receives a drug, the response can be the result of numerous factors:
• The pharmacodynamic effect of the drug and interactions with any other drugs the patient may be taking.
• The pharmacokinetics of the drug and its modification in the individual by genetic influences, disease, other drugs.
• The act of medication, including the route of administration and the presence or absence of the doctor.
• What the doctor has told the patient.
• The patient’s past experience of doctors.
• The patient’s estimate of what has been received and of what ought to happen as a result.
• The social environment, e.g. whether it is supportive or dispiriting.
Drugs can do harm
Efficacy and safety do not lie solely in the molecular structure of the drug. Doctors must choose which drugs to use and must apply them correctly in relation not only to their properties, but also to those of the patients and their disease. Then patients must use the prescribed medicine correctly (see Compliance p. 21).
Uses of drugs/medicines
Prevention
1. Should I interfere with the patient at all?
2. If so, what alteration in the patient’s condition do I hope to achieve?
3. Which drug is most likely to bring this about?
4. How can I administer the drug to attain the right concentration in the right place at the right time and for the right duration?
5. How will I know when I have achieved the objective?
6. What other effects might the drug produce, and are these harmful?
7. How will I decide to stop the drug?
8. Does the likelihood of benefit, and its importance, outweigh the likelihood of damage, and its importance, i.e. the benefit versus risk, or efficacy against safety?
Physician-induced (iatrogenic) disease
It is a salutary thought that each year medical errors kill an estimated 44 000–98 000 Americans (more than die in motor vehicle accidents) and injure 1 000 000.7 Among inpatients in the USA and Australia, about half of the injuries caused by medical mismanagement result from surgery, but therapeutic mishaps and diagnostic errors are the next most common. In one survey of adverse drug events, 1% were fatal, 12% life-threatening, 30% serious and 57% significant.8 About half of the life-threatening and serious events were preventable. Errors of prescribing account for one-half and those of administering drugs for one-quarter of these. Inevitably, a proportion of lapses result in litigation, and in the UK 20–25% of complaints received by the medical defence organisations about general practitioners follow medication errors.
The most shameful act in therapeutics, apart from actually killing a patient, is to injure a patient who is but little disabled or who is suffering from a self-limiting disorder. Such iatrogenic disease,9 induced by misguided treatment, is far from rare.
In 1917 the famous pharmacologist Sollmann felt able to write:
Pharmacology comprises some broad conceptions and generalisations, and some detailed conclusions, of such great and practical importance that every student and practitioner should be absolutely familiar with them. It comprises also a large mass of minute details, which would constitute too great a tax on human memory, but which cannot safely be neglected.10
Benefits and risks of medicines
Unavoidable risks
Consider, for the sake of argument, the features that a completely risk-free drug would exhibit:
• The physician would know exactly what action is required and use the drug correctly.
• The drug would deliver its desired action and nothing else, either by true biological selectivity or by selective targeted delivery.
• The drug would achieve exactly the right amount of action – neither too little, nor too much.
These criteria may be completely fulfilled, for example in a streptococcal infection sensitive to penicillin in patients whose genetic constitution does not render them liable to an allergic reaction to penicillin.
Some reasons why drugs fail to meet the criteria of being risk-free include the following:
• Drugs may be insufficiently selective. As the concentration rises, a drug that acts at only one site at low concentrations begins to affect other target sites (receptors, enzymes) and recruit new (unwanted) actions; or a disease process (cancer) is so close to normal cellular mechanisms that perfectly selective cell kill is impossible.
• Drugs may be highly selective for one pathway but the mechanism affected has widespread functions and interference with it cannot be limited to one site only, e.g. atenolol on the β-adrenoceptor, aspirin on cyclo-oxygenase.
• Prolonged modification of cellular mechanisms can lead to permanent change in structure and function, e.g. carcinogenicity.
• Insufficient knowledge of disease processes (some cardiac arrhythmias) and of drug action can lead to interventions that, although undertaken with the best intentions, are harmful.
• Patients are genetically heterogeneous to a high degree and may have unpredicted responses to drugs.
• Dosage adjustment according to need is often unavoidably imprecise, e.g. in depression.
Reduction of risk
Strategies that can limit risk include those directed at achieving:
Two broad categories of risk
1. First are those that we accept by deliberate choice. We do so even if we do not exactly know their magnitude, or we know but wish they were smaller, or, especially when the likelihood of harm is sufficiently remote though the consequences may be grave, we do not even think about the matter. Such risks include transport and sports, both of which are inescapably subject to potent physical laws such as gravity and momentum, and surgery to rectify disorders that we could tolerate or treat in other ways, as with much cosmetic surgery.
2. Second are those risks that cannot be significantly altered by individual action. We experience risks imposed by food additives (preservatives, colouring), air pollution and some environmental radioactivity. But there are also risks imposed by nature, such as skin cancer due to excess ultraviolet radiation in sunny climes, as well as some radioactivity.
It seems an obvious course to avoid unnecessary risks, but there is disagreement on what risks are truly unnecessary and, on looking closely at the matter, it is plain that many people habitually take risks in their daily and recreational life that it would be a misuse of words to describe as necessary. Furthermore, some risks, although known to exist, are, in practice, ignored other than by conforming to ordinary prudent conduct. These risks are negligible in the sense that they do not influence behaviour, i.e. they are neglected.12
Elements of risk
There is general agreement that drugs prescribed for disease are themselves the cause of a significant amount of disease (adverse reactions), of death, of permanent disability, of recoverable illness and of minor inconvenience. In one major UK study the prevalence of adverse drug reactions as a cause of admission to hospital was 6.5% (see Chapter 9 for other examples).
Three major grades of risk
Risks are among the facts of life. In whatever we do and in whatever we refrain from doing, we are accepting risk. Some risks are obvious, some are unsuspected and some we conceal from ourselves. But risks are universally accepted, whether willingly or unwillingly, whether consciously or not.13
Whenever a drug is taken a risk is taken
In some chronic diseases that ultimately necessitate suppressive drugs, the patient may not experience benefit in the early stages. Patients with early Parkinson’s disease may experience little inconvenience or hazard from the condition, and premature exposure to drugs can exact such a price in unwanted effects that they prefer the untreated state. What patients will tolerate depends on their personality, their attitude to disease, their occupation, mode of life and relationship with their doctor (see Compliance, p. 21).
Public view of drugs and prescribers
There are obvious areas where some remedial action is possible:
• Improvement of prescribing by doctors, including better communication with patients, i.e. doctors must learn to feel that introduction of foreign chemicals into their patients’ bodies is a serious matter, which many or most do not seem to feel at present.14
• Introduction of no-fault compensation schemes for serious drug injury (some countries already have these).
• Informed public discussion of the issues between the medical profession, industrial drug developers, politicians and other ‘opinion-formers’ in society, and patients (the public).
• Restraint in promotion by the pharmaceutical industry including self-control by both industry and doctors in their necessarily close relationship, which the public is inclined to regard as a conspiracy, especially when the gifts and payments made to doctors get into the news. (This is much less prevalent than it was in the 1990s.)
If restraint by both parties is not forthcoming, and it may not be, then both doctor and industry can expect even more control to be exercised over them by politicians responding to public demand. If doctors do not want their prescribing to be restricted, they should prescribe better.
Criticisms of modern drugs
Two examples of inappropriate measurements will suffice:
1. In the case of many infections it is not disputed that environmental changes have had a greater beneficial effect on health than the subsequently introduced antimicrobials. But this does not mean that environmental improvements alone are sufficient in the fight against infections. When comparisons of illnesses in the pre- and post-antimicrobial eras are made, like is not compared with like. Environmental changes achieved their results when mortality from infections was high and antimicrobials were not available; antimicrobials were introduced later against a background of low mortality as well as of environmental change; decades separate the two parts of the comparison, and observers, diagnostic criteria and data recording changed during this long period. It is evident that determining the value of antimicrobials is not simply a matter of looking at mortality rates.
2. About 1% of the UK population has diabetes mellitus, a figure which is increasing rapidly, and about 1% of death certificates mention diabetes. This is no surprise because all must die and insulin is no cure15 for this lifelong disease. A standard medical textbook of 1907 stated that juvenile-onset ‘diabetes is in all cases a grave disease, and the subjects are regarded by all assurance companies as uninsurable lives: life seems to hang by a thread, a thread often cut by a very trifling accident’. Most, if not all, life insurance companies now accept young people with diabetes with no or only modest financial penalty, the premium of a person 5–10 years older. Before insulin replacement therapy was available few survived beyond 3 years16 after diagnosis; they died for lack of insulin. It is unjustified to assert that a treatment is worthless just because its mention on death certificates (whether as a prime or as a contributory cause) has not declined. The relevant criteria for juvenile-onset diabetes are change in the age at which the subjects die and the quality of life between diagnosis and death, and both of these have changed enormously.
Drug-induced injury17 (see also Ch. 9)
Negligence and strict and no-fault liability
All civilised legal systems provide for compensation to be paid to a person injured as a result of using a product of any kind that is defective due to negligence (fault: failure to exercise reasonable care).18 But there is a growing opinion that special compensation for serious personal injury, beyond the modest sums that general social security systems provide, should be automatic and not dependent on fault and proof of fault of the producer, i.e. there should be ‘liability irrespective of fault’, ‘no-fault liability’ or ‘strict liability’.19 After all, victims need assistance (compensation) regardless of the cause of injury and whether or not the producer and, in the case of drugs, the prescriber deserves censure. The question why a person who has suffered injury due to the biological accident of disease should have to depend on social security payments while an identical injury due to a drug (in the absence of fault) should attract special added compensation receives no persuasive answer except that this is what society seems to want.
Many countries are now revising their laws on liability for personal injury due to manufactured products and are legislating Consumer Protection Acts (Statutes) which include medicines, for ‘drugs represent the class of product in respect of which there has been the greatest pressure for surer compensation in cases of injury’.20
Issues that are central to the debate include:
• Capacity to cause harm is inherent in drugs in a way that sets them apart from other manufactured products; and harm often occurs in the absence of fault.
• Safety, i.e. the degree of safety that a person is entitled to expect, and adverse effects that should be accepted without complaint, must often be a matter of opinion and will vary with the disease being treated, e.g. cancer or insomnia.
• Causation, i.e. proof that the drug in fact caused the injury, is often impossible, particularly where it increases the incidence of a disease that occurs naturally.
• Contributory negligence. Should compensation be reduced in smokers and drinkers where there is evidence that these pleasure drugs increase liability to adverse reactions to therapeutic drugs?
• The concept of defect, i.e. whether the drug or the prescriber or indeed the patient can be said to be ‘defective’ so as to attract liability, is a highly complex matter and indeed is a curious concept as applied to medicine.
Nowhere has a scheme that meets all the major difficulties yet been implemented. This is not because there has been too little thought, it is because the subject is so difficult. Nevertheless, no-fault schemes operate in New Zealand, Scandinavia and France.21 The following principles might form the basis of a workable compensation scheme for injury due to drugs:
• New unlicensed drugs undergoing clinical trial in small numbers of subjects (healthy or patient volunteers): the developer should be strictly liable for all adverse effects.
• New unlicensed drugs undergoing extensive trials in patients who may reasonably expect benefit: the producer should be strictly liable for any serious effect.
• New drugs after licensing by an official body: the manufacturer and the community should share liability for serious injury, as new drugs provide general benefit. An option might be to institute a defined period of formal prospective drug surveillance monitoring, in which both doctors and patients agree to participate.
• Standard drugs in day-to-day therapeutics: there should be a no-fault scheme, operated by or with the assent of government that has authority, through tribunals, to decide cases quickly and to make awards. This body would have authority to reimburse itself from others – manufacturer, supplier, prescriber – wherever that was appropriate. An award must not have to wait on the outcome of prolonged, vexatious, adversarial, expensive court proceedings. Patients would be compensated where: